Stoicism, REBT & Albert Ellis

What disturbs people's minds are not events but their judgements on events

Seek not that the things which happen should happen as you wish; but wish the things which happen to be as they are, and you will have a tranquil flow of life.

Men are not worried by things, but by their ideas about things. When we meet difficulties, become anxious or troubled, let us not blame others, but rather ourselves, that is: our idea about things.

Some things are up to us and some are not up to us. Our opinions are up to us, our impulses, desires, aversions, in-short whatever is our doing. Our bodies are not up to us, nor our possessions, our reputations, or our public offices, or that is, whatever is not of our own doing.

--Epictetus 





Stoicism teaches self-control and detachment from distracting emotions, sometimes interpreted as an indifference to pleasure or pain. Stoics believe that this allows one to be a clear thinker, level-headed and unbiased. In practice, Stoicism is intended to imbue an individual with virtue, wisdom, and integrity of character. Students are encouraged to be altruistic as well as psychologically independent from society, regarding it as an unruly and often unreasonable entity while encouraging active engagement in improving society.

Virtue, reason, and natural law are prime directives. By mastering passions and emotions, stoics believe it is possible to overcome the discord of the outside world and find peace within oneself. Stoicism holds that passion distorts truth, and that the pursuit of truth is virtuous.

http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Stoicism




The Stoics’ core message was that human emotions are not passive reactions but are subject to cognitive control. Thoughts, opinions and interpretations cause, mediate and shape emotions, which the Stoics saw as something of an act of judgment and will, and a matter of our own responsibility. But Stoicism can also become extreme, enabling individuals to detach themselves to survive or to kill, which sometimes leaves the doer with lasting trauma.

http://www.amazon.com/gp/product/0195152166/




The Stoics held that emotions like fear or envy (or impassioned sexual attachments, or passionate love of anything whatsoever) either were, or arose from, false judgements and that the sage--a person who had attained moral and intellectual perfection--would not undergo them. 

The later Stoics of Roman Imperial times, Seneca and Epictetus, emphasise the doctrines (already central to the early Stoics' teachings) that the sage is utterly immune to misfortune and that virtue is sufficient for happiness. 

Our phrase ‘stoic calm’ perhaps encapsulates the general drift of these claims. 

When considering the doctrines of the Stoics, it is important to remember that they think of philosophy not as an interesting pastime or even a particular body of knowledge, but as a way of life. They define philosophy as a kind of practice or exercise in the expertise concerning what is beneficial. Once we come to know what we and the world around us are really like, and especially the nature of value, we will be utterly transformed.

http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/stoicism/



Stoicism Albert Ellis & Cognitive Behavioral Therapy

Rational Emotive Behaviour Therapy (REBT) is based on the concept that emotions and behaviours result from cognitive processes; and that it is possible for human beings to modify such processes to achieve different ways of feeling and behaving. REBT is one of a number of cognitive-behavioral therapies, which, although developed separately, have many similarities such as Cognitive Therapy (CT), developed by Psychiatrist Aaron Beck in the 1960s.  

In the mid-1950s Dr. Albert Ellis, a clinical psychologist trained in psychoanalysis, became disillusioned with the slow progress of his clients. He observed that they tended to get better when they changed their ways of thinking about themselves, their problems, and the world. Ellis reasoned that therapy would progress faster if the focus was directly on the clients beliefs, and thus was born the method now known as Rational Emotive Behaviour Therapy.

A Brief Introduction to Rational Emotive Behaviour Therapy

By Wayne Froggatt

https://www.scribd.com/document/21415924/Brief-Intro-to-CBT




REBT was influenced by the writing of the stoic philosophers. I mention that when I give presentations, whether at gatherings of psychologists or at a gathering like this Stoicon, and Al [Albert Ellis] acknowledged that influence when he spoke and when he wrote about the development of his approach.

There were other influences but some of the main tenets of REBT include ideas seen in Stoic writings, so I pointed that out as I went along in my workshop.  I described the main aspects of REBT and what sets it apart from the other approaches, particularly the cognitive ones, because REBT is the approach that heralded in the cognitive revolution in psychotherapy. Before it came along in the early 1950s, Sigmund Freud was the lord of the psychotherapeutic universe.

My husband was the first one in the field of psychology to so effectively challenge the tenets of psychoanalysis. In so doing, he received criticism and hatred – and was branded as “stupid” and “superficial” and worse than that.  But he continued on with his efforts because he believed so strongly in the efficacy of his approach and the efficiency of REBT. One can rightly say that he applied some of the stoic principles in his choice to not be affected by the barbs of others. He persevered in doing and sharing what he believed was most helpful for most humans, and as a result he succeeded in changing the world of psychotherapy and other fields.

Al saw REBT as not only the way to minimize emotional disturbance, but more than that – to create a life of quality, a life of self-created meaning that contributes not only to one’s self, but to the well-being of other humans and to the environment. REBT is a very holistic approach and way of being. In my view it is the most holistic approach of all the approaches in my field that I know of.

There are some misconceptions and false impressions about REBT. I don’t know if Epictetus or Marcus Aurelius or the other Stoics suffered from such things – because I think their place in history is seen as secure, along with their writings.

My husband wrote his first paper about REBT, which was then just called RT – “rational therapy” – in 1953. It was published in 1955. The Cognitive Therapy approach of Aaron Beck, came out fifteen years later, and he has acknowledged the help of my husband in creating the approach. Beck is part of the University of Pennsylvania, which has done enormous research on CBT, and I think that’s one of the reasons CBT is so well known.  There wasn’t that volume of research done on REBT. Nonetheless, the research done on CBT unsurprisingly supports the premises of REBT because much of CBT is based on the premises of REBT.

Interestingly, some of the misconceptions about REBT include that it came after CBT, or that it’s an offshoot of CBT.  Now there are newer cognitive approaches, some referred to as part of the “Third Wave” of cognitive approaches. One can recognize the components of REBT and Epictetus within them, and sadly, most of them don’t give credit where credit is due...

Rational Emotive Behavior Therapy and Stoicism – An Interview with Debbie Joffe Ellis 

http://modernstoicism.com/rational-emotive-behavior-therapy-rebt-and-stoicism-a-workshop-by-debbie-joffe-ellis/




Stoicism and CBT: Is Therapy a Philosophical Pursuit?

Are CBT’s main goals to stay in the present moment, like its original form (REBT) prescribed, by;

1. learning how to recognize habitual emotional response patterns, then

2. learning to interrupt them when they interfere with concentration on important parts of the moment and

3. slowly develop long-term replacement thinking habits which don’t cause such distracting arousal?

Many critics incorrectly believe that by learning to control emotional habits the learning process causes one to censor important aspects of life, but in reality uncontrolled emotional habits might cause one to more easily lose their life.

We might need to settle the problem of the criterion first; what is CBT and what are CBT’s goals?

“What disturbs people's minds are not events but their judgements on events..." 

--Epictetus


When you make the decision to seek counseling or therapy, you are in part making the decision to consult an applied philosopher — your therapist just may not know it! Cognitive-Behavioral Therapy (CBT) is one of the most well-known treatment models for anxiety, depression, and substance abuse — you’d be hard-pressed to find a psychotherapist who does not use any aspect of CBT in his or her practice. But CBT is also deeply indebted to the Stoic philosophers of ancient Greece.


Stoicism in Ancient Greece

Stoicism is a school of philosophy that rose to prominence in Greece during the 3rd Century B.C. No psychologists, psychiatrists, or therapists existed at this time; philosophers, instead, were the “physicians of the soul.” The Greeks found guidance with philosophy alone, and Stoicism was a particularly useful tool for self-improvement.

Stoicism arose during the Hellenistic period — the time after Alexander the Great and before the rise of the Roman Empire. Stoicism, like all philosophies, is a method of understanding the world and how we relate to it. Stoics believed truth is rooted in natural law, and that aligning one’s thoughts and expectations with natural order will promote mental well-being and protect against unnecessary emotional pain. Conversely, holding a belief contrary to nature laws will lead to unmet expectations and, in turn, suffering.

During the era of the Stoics, philosophy was accessible to all social classes, and was more important than ever in the daily lives of average citizens. More than wisdom for abstract purposes, Stoicism was practical, applicable, and effective. It was so useful that many of its core concepts are still in use today.

Cognitive-behavioral therapy in modern times

Fast-forward a couple thousand years. Psychologist Albert Ellis has just set forth the first cognitive-behavioral therapy, Rational Emotive Behavioral Therapy (REBT). With REBT, Ellis proposed that emotional and behavioral problems could be relieved by identifying and changing faulty thoughts and beliefs. He called this treatment model cognitive restructuring, and it represented a major shift in psychotherapy. Before Ellis, Freudian psychoanalysis, which emphasized the bringing forward of subconscious thoughts as a way of changing behaviors, had reigned.

Where did Ellis get his ideas? Epictetus, the Stoic philosopher, was perhaps his biggest source of inspiration. Ellis drew on Epictetus’ notion that our interpretations of events have a greater impact on us that the events themselves. The more unrealistic — or out of line with nature — our interpretations are, the more we suffer when our expectations aren’t met. Conversely, when our beliefs and expectations align with nature, we will  enjoy a well-adjusted life.

In the 1960s, another psychologist, Aaron Beck, identified fifteen specific ways in which our beliefs can drift away from reality and cause depression, anxiety, and other difficulties. He called these cognitive distortions, and he, too, believed that aligning one’s beliefs with natural order would reduce suffering. Sound familiar? His work was built on the framework of the Stoicism.

What do Stoicism and CBT have in common?

Stoicism and CBT overlap in several important ways. We will now look at three tenets of Stoicism that form the framework of cognitive-behavioral therapy: logic, acceptance, and control.

Logic

Stoics believed that the mind functions as an intermediary between our impressions (perceptions) and actions. A wise mind, they said, can successfully differentiate between accurate and faulty impressions through the use of logic. True impressions are based in observable laws of nature, and are to be assimilated into one’s worldview and acted upon. False impressions have no natural basis, and lead to destructive and painful emotions.

Therefore, logic is rooted in natural law, and negative emotions occur when we hold false or illogical beliefs about natural law. These could be beliefs about the physical world, or human nature. Instead of trying to change nature — an impossibility — a Stoic would realign his or her thoughts to more accurately reflect nature. In finding this harmony, the Stoic would reduce suffering.

Acceptance

Stoics believed all of nature is to be accepted, even its more tragic elements — death, loss, pain, misfortune, etc. These things occur naturally, so they are a part of natural law. To life a well-adjusted life, we must accept our strengths and limitations, as well as the beauties and horrors of the world.

Stoics were skeptical of overly optimistic or pessimistic judgments. After all, nature isn’t all good, or all bad — we are recipients of good and bad fortune. Stoics sought to live mindfully and non-judgmentally, accepting life as it comes without forming rigid expectations about the future.

Critics of Stoicism have accused the Stoics of being too passive — too willing to accept injustices of the world as a fact of life. However, Stoics paid great attention to locus of control, or the extent to which one’s can influence one’s circumstances. They believed in taking action when it mattered.

Control

Stoics recognized we don’t have complete control over our circumstances– our reputations, the way people treat us, etc. But we do have control over our own thoughts and beliefs. They believed we should concentrate our energy into these things we truly do control, and that doing so will give us the best opportunity to influence the world around us for the better.

With ethical action, the Stoics believed each individual could do his or her part to combat social ills. Everything else is outside our control, and we had better accept it.

These three things — using logical thought to identify unrealistic beliefs, accepting our circumstances, and making the distinction between the things we can and cannot control, are core tenets of cognitive-behavioral therapy. These can be seen in Aaron Beck’s original list of cognitive distortions: catastrophization, all-or-nothing thinking, and magnification and minimization are faults of logic that can lead to destructive emotions; jumping to conclusions, mind reading, and fortune telling are examples of failure to accept that which we do not know; and personalization and overgeneralization are mistakes of locus of control.

Stoicism and CBT: a difference of scope

Despite the similarities outlined above, Stoicism and cognitive-behavioral therapy do diverge in significant ways. The most significant difference, perhaps, is one of scope.

Stoicism has a metaphysical component

Many Stoics, including Epictetus, ascribed to fatalism. They believed that our fates are out of our control, and that the best we can do is dispassionately accept whatever our fates may be.

Today, fatalism is most often viewed within a religious context — believing a higher power has predetermined one’s life, for example.  For ancient Greeks, the bounds of religion were a bit blurrier than they are today, and many philosophies incorporated some ideas about the workings of the universe that we now would consider to be religious in nature.

CBT has no metaphysical component

Cognitive-Behavioral Therapy has a more limited scope, and does not posit any hypotheses about the greater workings of the universe, or a higher power. CBT is merely a therapeutic tool, though a powerful one.*

*Speaking of scope, there are also a number of core Stoic beliefs, and branches of Stoic thought, that are outside the scope of this article (a good primer on Stoicism can be found here).

Is therapy a philosophical pursuit?

The role of the cognitive-behavioral therapist today has many similarities to the role of a Stoic philosopher in ancient Greece. Far from being an academic interest, Stoic philosophy permeated the everyday life of its practitioners.

When we remember ancient Greece, its famous philosophers come quickly to mind.  They, and Stoics in particular, believed that mastering one’s perception is an essential part of living successfully in the world.

When you make the decision to engage in psychotherapy, particularly cognitive-behavioral therapy, you’re taking part in an ancient tradition. The emphasis ancient Greeks put on the understanding of the mind, mental wellness, and the relationship between the mind and the natural world, cannot be overstated. Therapy is a powerful tool for understanding and change, and has been for thousands of years.

Understanding the lineage from ancient Stoicism to cognitive-behavioral therapy makes the American stigma about mental health treatment all the more unfortunate. Our culture continues to celebrate our debt to ancient Greek advancements in countless other ways. Stoicism has been embraced by mainstream society more and more lately, including, of all places, the NFL. Increasing public awareness of the influence Stoicism has had on modern psychotherapy, specifically Stoicism and CBT, can help to reduce the stigma of mental health treatment.

References:

Beck, Aaron T. (1972). Depression; Causes and Treatment. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.

Ellis, Albert; Debbie Joffe Ellis (2011). Rational Emotive Behavior Therapy. American Psychological Association.

Epictetus; Long, George (trans.) Enchiridion.  New York: A. L. Burt, 1955 (reprint: New York: Dover, 2004)

Robertson, Donald. (2010). The Philosophy of Cognitive-Behavioral Therapy (CBT): Stoic Philosophy as Rational and Cognitive Psychotherapy. Karnac Books.


Stoicism and CBT: Is Therapy a Philosophical Pursuit?

https://www.vacounseling.com/stoicism-cbt/


Stoicism Ellis & Cognitive Behavioral Therapy

http://philosophy-of-cbt.com/the-philosophy-of-cognitive-behavioural-therapy/




Stoic-Warriors: The Ancient Philosophy Behind The Military Mind 

While few soldiers may have read the works of Epictetus or Marcus Aurelius, it is undoubtedly true that the ancient philosophy known as Stoicism guides the actions of many in the military. Soldiers and seamen learn early in their training "to suck it up," to endure, to put aside their feelings and to get on with the mission.

Stoic Warriors is the first book to delve deeply into the ancient legacy of this relationship, exploring what the Stoic philosophy actually is, the role it plays in the character of the military (both ancient and modern), and its powerful value as a philosophy of life. Marshalling anecdotes from military history--ranging from ancient Greek wars to World War II, Vietnam, and Iraq--Nancy Sherman illuminates the military mind and uses it as a window on the virtues of the Stoic philosophy, which are far richer and more interesting than our popularized notions. Sherman--a respected philosopher who taught at the US Naval Academy--explores the deep, lasting value that Stoicism can yield, in issues of military leadership and character; in the Stoic conception of anger and its control (does a warrior need anger to go to battle?); and in Stoic thinking about fear and resilience, grief and mourning, and the value of camaraderie and brotherhood. Sherman concludes by recommending a moderate Stoicism, where the task for the individual, both civilian and military, youth and adult, is to temper control with forgiveness, and warrior drive and achievement with humility and humor.

Here then is a perceptive investigation of what makes Stoicism so compelling not only as a guiding principle for the military, but as a philosophy for anyone facing the hardships of life.

https://www.nancysherman.com/the-stoic-warrior




Stoic Warriors: The Ancient Philosophy behind the Military Mind - Nancy Sherman 

Chapter Summaries


Abstract


While few soldiers may have read the works of Epictetus or Marcus Aurelius, it is undoubtedly true that the ancient philosophy known as Stoicism guides the actions of many in the military. Soldiers and seamen learn early in their training “to suck it up,” to endure, to put aside their feelings and to get on with the mission. This book explores what the Stoic philosophy actually is, the role it plays in the character of the military (both ancient and modern), and its powerful value as a philosophy of life. Marshaling anecdotes from military history—ranging from ancient Greek wars to World War II, Vietnam, and Iraq—the book illuminates the military mind and uses it as a window on the virtues of the Stoic philosophy, which are far richer and more interesting than our popularized notions. The book explores the deep, lasting value that Stoicism can yield, in issues of military leadership and character; in the Stoic conception of anger and its control (does a warrior need anger to go to battle?); and in Stoic thinking about fear and resilience, grief and mourning, and the value of camaraderie and brotherhood. The book concludes by recommending a moderate Stoicism, where the task for the individual, both civilian and military, youth and adult, is to temper control with forgiveness, and warrior drive and achievement with humility and humor.


Chapter 1; A Brave New Stoicism


This chapter provides an overview of the philosophy of Stoicism and its influence in the military. The experience of James B. Stockdale is an extreme application of Stoicism. Stockdale, a senior Navy pilot shot down over Vietnam, became a prisoner of war during the Vietnam War. He credits Epictetus as the key to his survival for seven-and-a-half years of his life in military prison. For Stockdale, prison can offer an extreme experiment in Stoicism. It was there that even the most brute external forces—such as repeated, severe torture—still demanded something of the will and mind, something that could be parlayed into the Stoic category “what belongs to oneself” and “what is within one's power.” On his telling, it was his Epictetan Stoicism that enabled him to regain his dignity if and when he broke in torture.


Chapter 2; Sound Bodies and Sound Minds


This chapter discusses the issue of discipline as it affects the development of both mind and body. It explores whether Stoic teachings about our relationship with our bodies offer sage counsel. Americans have become a culture obsessed with physical fitness and the demands of fashioning a hard, strong body. The stripped-down life of military endurance offers something of a model of discipline and control. The view seems Stoic, but ancient Stoics view bodily health and vigor as “indifferents,” that is, external goods, not valuable in their own right or fully within our control. Stoic doctrines force the questions of how we are to live with the fragility of our bodies, what efforts we are to put into their adornment and sculpture, and what attitudes we are to take when our bodies fail us.


Chapter 3; Manners and Morals


This chapter considers the important role that manners and demeanor play in the cultivation of virtue. It explores the emphasis in military training on things that are “outer”—appearances, decorum, deference rituals, and demeanor. The issue is central to the military and its core belief that training in decorum is an integral part of training character. This chapter also discusses Stoic texts and the insights one can glean from Stoic theory on issues of decorum and emotional demeanor. Cicero, in On Duties, reports a Stoic view that decorum is inextricably woven into the fabric of virtuous character. Seneca, in On Favors argues for the crucial role of emotional demeanor in acts of kindness and gratitude. Both accounts recognize an individual's propensity for emotional expression and the reasonable expectation of it as part of respectful social exchange.


Chapter 4; A Warrior's Anger


This chapter discusses the Stoic conception of anger and the control of anger. It examines the Stoic view that anger is a dangerous emotion that can torment both its possessor and the human beings who are its object. In response to the excesses of anger, the Stoics proposed their own extreme measure: to do away with anger entirely. They proposed an apatheia—a freedom from passions in which there is no frenzy or rage, no annoyance or bitterness, no moral outrage. The recurrent question in ancient texts from Homer to Seneca is whether a warrior needs anger to go to battle or not. Seneca, like many moderns, says no, but then he proceeded to eliminate other, more constructive forms of anger that might be essential to good moral character in general.


Chapter 5; Fear and Resilience


This chapter explores Stoic conceptions of fear and resilience. It assesses the notion of replacing fear with a sage's rational caution, and the cost in terms of acknowledging human vulnerability. Both Seneca and Cicero, in quite different ways, shed light on understanding these fears. This chapter also illustrates some concrete examples of fear in battle and considers both the fear of killing and being killed and the challenge of transitioning from the role of soldier to civilian. Finally, this chapter discusses contemporary notions of war trauma and the insights ancient Stoicism sheds on the nature of resilience in the face of extreme terror and stress.


Chapter 6; Permission to Grieve


This chapter discusses grief and the Stoic notions of mourning and appropriate decorum in grieving. Cicero's candid reflections about the loss of his beloved daughter Tullia in letters, and his developed ideas about a therapy of grief in the Tusculan Disputations, provide some of the most insightful writings on this subject. This chapter argues that the question of how and whether one should grieve is reflected deep in the dialectic of Stoic discourse itself. It begins with several objections Seneca raised to specific forms of grief as well as his own proposals for acceptable forms of grief. It then turns to Cicero's analysis and his recommendations for both the reduction of grief and its cure. Throughout, this chapter generously draws on illustrations from the military as ways of assessing Stoic claims.


Chapter 7; The Downsized Self


This chapter discusses camaraderie, empathy, and respect. It looks at camaraderie as a critical element in combat courage and resilience, and as essential to psychological recovery in the aftermath of war. Here Stoicism is extremely illuminating, with clear lessons about the roles of respect and empathy necessary for building a sense of humanity and global community. This chapter examines many expressions of human fellowship central to the military, from the camaraderie and twinship of war buddies to the therapeutic bond between shell shock patient and psychiatrist, and to notions of ourselves as citizens of the world who share in reason. Diogenes the Cynic's ideal of a cosmopolitan community remains an ideal toward which the international community is only slowly making progress. And yet each of us, civilian, or soldier, as citizen of the world, must do his or her part to realize the ideal.


Stoic Warriors: The Ancient Philosophy behind the Military Mind - Oxford Scholarship

https://oxford.universitypressscholarship.com/view/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195315912.001.0001/acprof-9780195315912




Stoic Warriors: The Ancient Philosophy behind the Military Mind


Nancy Sherman, Stoic Warriors: The Ancient Philosophy behind the Military Mind, Oxford University Press, 2005, 256pp, $26.00 (hbk), ISBN 0195152166. 

Reviewed by Christopher Toner, Air University


Nancy Sherman notes at the outset that the idea of "being stoic" resonates with military officers, but notes also that there are severe costs to being Stoic in a rigorous, orthodox fashion. Interweaving an investigation of topics in Stoic philosophy with an exploration of "the military mind" and its ways of dealing with the rigors of military life and combat, she argues that a modified or "gentle Stoicism" provides the psychological and moral outlook suitable for the military, and in many ways for the rest of us as well. This view, culled largely from the Roman Stoics, still stresses and seeks to empower autonomous rational agency, while acknowledging human limits and human sociability in ways alien to some of the more rigorous Greek Stoics -- indeed in ways that frequently invoke Aristotle. So much is this the case, in fact, that I will finally ask how Stoic Sherman's warriors will really be: might they instead be, in a phrase no publisher would accept in the title of a book, Peripatetic Warriors?


Before asking this question, of course, I should examine Sherman's treatment of the broadly if pre-philosophically stoic nature of the military mind, and how she thinks it could profit by becoming in some respects more, and in others less, Stoic. As the book is a (successful, I think) attempt to write for at least three audiences -- philosophers, military officers, and a wider morally reflective public -- she begins with an overview of Stoic moral thought (their notions of happiness, self-control and the emotions, choosing goods as contrasted with selecting indifferents) and an introduction to her key sources: Cicero, Seneca, Epictetus, and Marcus Aurelius. She focuses on the Romans because we have their complete texts, and because they took it as their object to present a publicly accessible and practical philosophy. Her broaching the topic of the bearing of Stoic philosophy on military life with the story of Admiral James Stockdale's reliance on Epictetus as a prisoner of war in Vietnam is typical of her approach in this book, and it is effective: Stoicism is not merely a theory, but can powerfully inform a practical outlook on life and can guide and strengthen vulnerable human beings facing extreme hardships and the violent emotions attendant upon them.


The second chapter contrasts current obsessions with physical fitness (taken to dangerous extremes by some body builders) with Stoic indifference to the body -- the body is external to happiness, and is to be regarded as a tool, to be kept in good condition, to be sure, but not valued for its own sake. Here the resonance with a military outlook is clear: physical fitness is a duty because of its role in mission readiness, and further, given the high risks to which the body is subjected, one can see some appeal in regarding it as a preferred indifferent. Yet Sherman pulls back: Drawing on anecdotes of soldiers who have lost limbs or suffered other disfiguring injuries, she argues that while Stoicism has much to offer in service of recovering or at least adapting, we should be prepared to admit, as even the most stoic of the veterans do, that such injuries can indeed affect our happiness and even our sense of identity.


Sherman then turns to the role of decorum in instilling military bearing of the sort that can maintain good order and discipline even in combat conditions, largely defending the military's use of manners to instill morals, if I may so put it. In doing so, Sherman draws on Cicero's notion of decorum being indexed to our roles or personae (noting that this notion usefully allows us to separate the deferential respect due to rank and based on one's professional role, from the dignitary respect due to all and based on our shared, and most fundamental, role as rational agents), and Seneca's account of how decorum and emotional demeanor can help "weave the fabric of community." The decorum insisted upon by the military, focusing on stolid determination, respect and obedience, and camaraderie and friendship between soldiers, can cement the bonds within military units (bonds shown in many studies to be essential to combat effectiveness); the approach to decorum taken by enlightened commanders can be enriched by familiarity with Stoic treatments of the subject. It is in this chapter that we find the most direct and unmixed recommendation of Stoic views; the remaining chapters deal largely with emotion in Stoic theory and in the life of the warrior, and while Sherman certainly finds much of value in the former, she repeatedly softens or even controverts key Stoic claims, often leaning in the direction of Aristotle.


Her first topic is anger, and she begins by noting the Stoic view that apatheia must replace anger, which is both destructive and a sign of vulnerability. Following an interesting discussion of how mock anger can be more effective than real anger in military training and inculturation (in Boot Camp, e.g.), she turns to Seneca's famous treatment of anger and its role in frenzy and cruelty in De Ira. But while she endorses some of his warnings about anger, she insists that some forms of anger, such as righteous indignation, can, as protests of moral violations and expressions of commitment to value, be healthy and just. This she illustrates with two stories. The first is that of Hugh Thomson at My Lai: the Army warrant officer, acting in part from a sense of moral outrage, had his crew train their guns on involved American soldiers and was able to prevent part of that day's massacre. The second, perhaps of particular interest to philosophers, is that of John Rawls's experience of anger during the Second World War, an anger directed not at civilians or even at foot soldiers, but at the Japanese leaders. Sherman concludes that while the Stoics are certainly right that anger cannot simply be given free reign, neither should (or can) it be simply eliminated or even repressed and compartmentalized. The emotions will find expression in some form, and we should work toward ensuring that that form is rational. As Aristotle said, in a passage Sherman cites in this chapter, we must be angry in the right way with the right people for the right reasons.


Sherman turns next to another emotion prominent in war: fear. The rigorous Stoic view is that all fear is irrational because it treats external dangers to life and limb as genuine evils that can affect our happiness. Sherman rejects this view -- "the unacceptable face of orthodox Stoicism" -- because it alienates us from our humanity in the sense that it regards our commitments to bodily integrity and to family and friends, all things that can be lost suddenly and terribly in war, as indifferents. Fear of such things is natural and just -- so also is the fear of killing others (surely we do not want to eradicate this entirely even in soldiers). But drawing on Seneca and Cicero she proposes that a moderate Stoicism can brace us for tragedy and help us recover from it without compromising our humanity. Of particular interest here is her suggestion that soldiers need become adept at "role switching," between their professional role as warrior and their more fundamental role as human beings, a role they should be always ready to bring back to the fore. Sherman closes with a discussion of how some Stoic ideals, such as a resumed sense of empowered agency, have proven effective in recovering from post-traumatic stress disorder.


The last two chapters, on grief and camaraderie, both focus on the importance of solidarity in military life, and play out largely in the pattern we have seen so far: the orthodox Stoic claims are stated, rejected as too strong (Sherman notes a tension between the Stoic conception of agents as both self-sufficient and as social beings), and a modified position with recognizably Stoic features advanced in their place. In softening the Stoic view that grief, as an expression of distress and vulnerability, is to be eliminated, Sherman draws on Seneca's and Cicero's writing on grieving with proper decorum, and interestingly links their ideas to traditional forms of military grieving, such as military funeral services and war memorials. Yet she seems to go further than they do, and to endorse Aristotle's idea that "the expression of certain emotions can be cathartic and a medium for enlightenment and purification." This point too, she shows, is borne out by military experience. Turning to camaraderie, she rightly notes that military life "requires a self-sufficiency that is social to the core," and allows that on "appreciating the role of friendship and the contribution of attachment emotions to psychological and moral sustenance, Aristotle and his followers simply do better": Stoics cannot admit, as they should, that friendship is essential to our self-sufficiency and well-being. Yet Sherman does insist that the Stoics outdo Aristotle on one vital form of commitment to community: the universal community of all rational agents, cemented by respect for human beings as such, whether or not we are emotionally attached to them. She connects this Stoic idea of human agents as citizens of the cosmos to Michael Walzer's idea of all combatants as moral equals participating in a hellish but still norm-governed activity, and points out that here is a lesson the military mind would do well to internalize (invoking, of course, the shameful story of Abu Ghraib). Realizing the ideal of a universal community, she concludes, "requires cultivating humanity through empathetic identification and respect," something that "should be a part of any warrior's code."


This is an impressive book, and in many ways a moving one, even a personal one (the stories related, occasionally with illustrating photographs, are powerful; some of them involve protagonists she came to know through her connection to the Naval Academy; one story relates her father's experiences as a medic during the Second World War). It offers a valuable treatment of Stoic philosophy, and of military culture, which she clearly understands and respects. Indeed readers will find here not so much groundbreaking research on Stoic texts or their interpretations as something more like a philosophy, or the core of a philosophy, of military service -- a philosophy of one of the fundamental professional roles in our culture, with implications for our most fundamental role of all, human agency. It is a practical book of philosophy -- in this too, then, Sherman follows the Roman Stoics. Still, the book does not leave us without a few points for critical notice.


Although the book is wide ranging (and I have not done justice to some of its features, such as the dialogue she opens between Stoicism and contemporary psychology), I believe it could usefully have ranged just enough further as to take up two other topics important in military life. Sexuality intermittently gets the military in trouble, and I suspect Sherman's modified Stoicism (perhaps taking Marcus Aurelius's views as a starting point) could shed some light on the subject. The other topic is religion: Sherman occasionally takes up religious themes (the religious beliefs of certain protagonists of her anecdotes, the kaddish or Jewish prayer of mourning), but I believe religion is rather more central to "the military mind" than she lets on: it is an old saying that there are no atheists in foxholes.


Finally, we have noted Sherman's reliance upon the Roman Stoics, something she herself stresses. But, does she follow them so far as to be Stoic herself? I think actually not. Her borrowings from Aristotle are not merely in service of filling in gaps in a Stoic account, but at times are in direct opposition to some quite central Stoic positions, as Sherman herself points out: "We might ultimately wish Seneca to concede a similar point: that loss of a beloved … can diminish our overall good or happiness (eudaimonia). But to concede this would undermine a cornerstone of Stoicism." Yet, as we have seen, she does concede it, e.g. in seeing friendship as actually part of happiness. It seems to me that it is Stoicism that is filling in gaps (sometimes important ones, to be sure) in an account that is fundamentally Aristotelian. Or perhaps we should say that her Stoicism is not merely unorthodox, but heretical, rejecting some quite central doctrines and occasionally following after strange gods. At the very least, Stoicism is not the (sole) ancient philosophy behind the military mind. I do not of course mean that Sherman is unaware of this, but neither do I mean here merely to quibble over words (and I am not seriously suggesting re-titling the book Peripatetic or -- heaven forbid -- Eclectic Warriors): Sherman leads us to take up the old question about how one should live, and I find it very interesting that, starting from a Stoic outlook, we continually find ourselves moving back to an Aristotelian one to get things quite right.


Stoic Warriors: The Ancient Philosophy behind the Military Mind | Reviews | Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews | University of Notre Dame

https://ndpr.nd.edu/reviews/stoic-warriors-the-ancient-philosophy-behind-the-military-mind/ 


Stoic Warriors a reflective essay 

by David J. Ladouceur 

http://www.combat.ws/S3/BAKISSUE/CMBT04N4/STOIC.HTM


Another Long Review; 
Sherman — Stoic Warriors – Chicago Boyz

Author: March 22, 2007 by James McCormick

Source: https://chicagoboyz.net/archives/4871.html



Our Biggest Fight

Reclaiming Liberty, Humanity, and Dignity in the Digital Age The internet as we know it is broken. Here’s how we can seize back contr...